翻訳と辞書
Words near each other
・ Proof of the Euler product formula for the Riemann zeta function
・ Proof of the Man
・ Proof of Youth
・ Proof positive
・ Proof Positive (album)
・ Proof Positive (Greene story)
・ Proof Positive (TV series)
・ Proof procedure
・ Proof School
・ Proof sketch for Gödel's first incompleteness theorem
・ Proof test
・ Proof that 22/7 exceeds π
・ Proof that e is irrational
・ Proof That the Youth Are Revolting
・ Proof that π is irrational
Proof theory
・ Proof Through the Night
・ Proof without words
・ Proof-carrying code
・ Proof-number search
・ Proof-of-payment
・ Proof-of-stake
・ Proof-of-work system
・ Proof-theoretic semantics
・ Proof/No Vain
・ Proofing
・ Proofing (armour)
・ Proofing (baking technique)
・ Proofpoint
・ Proofpoint Systems, Inc


Dictionary Lists
翻訳と辞書 辞書検索 [ 開発暫定版 ]
スポンサード リンク

Proof theory : ウィキペディア英語版
Proof theory
Proof theory is a branch of mathematical logic that represents proofs as formal mathematical objects, facilitating their analysis by mathematical techniques. Proofs are typically presented as inductively-defined data structures such as plain lists, boxed lists, or trees, which are constructed according to the axioms and rules of inference of the logical system. As such, proof theory is syntactic in nature, in contrast to model theory, which is semantic in nature. Together with model theory, axiomatic set theory, and recursion theory, proof theory is one of the so-called ''four pillars'' of the foundations of mathematics.〔E.g., Wang (1981), pp. 3–4, and Barwise (1978).〕
Some of the major areas of proof theory include structural proof theory, ordinal analysis, provability logic, reverse mathematics, proof mining, automated theorem proving, and proof complexity. Much research also focuses on applications in computer science, linguistics, and philosophy.
==History==
Although the formalisation of logic was much advanced by the work of such figures as Gottlob Frege, Giuseppe Peano, Bertrand Russell, and Richard Dedekind, the story of modern proof theory is often seen as being established by David Hilbert, who initiated what is called Hilbert's program in the foundations of mathematics. The central idea of this program was that if we could give finitary proofs of consistency for all the sophisticated formal theories needed by mathematicians, then we could ground these theories by means of a metamathematical argument, which shows that all of their purely universal assertions (more technically their provable \Pi^0_1 sentences) are finitarily true; once so grounded we do not care about the non-finitary meaning of their existential theorems, regarding these as pseudo-meaningful stipulations of the existence of ideal entities.
The failure of the program was induced by Kurt Gödel's incompleteness theorems, which showed that any ω-consistent theory that is sufficiently strong to express certain simple arithmetic truths, cannot prove its own consistency, which on Gödel's formulation is a \Pi^0_1 sentence. However, modified versions of Hilbert's program emerged and research has been carried out on related topics. This has led, in particular, to:
*Refinement of Gödel's result, particularly J. Barkley Rosser's refinement, weakening the above requirement of ω-consistency to simple consistency;
*Axiomatisation of the core of Gödel's result in terms of a modal language, provability logic;
*Transfinite iteration of theories, due to Alan Turing and Solomon Feferman;
*The recent discovery of self-verifying theories, systems strong enough to talk about themselves, but too weak to carry out the diagonal argument that is the key to Gödel's unprovability argument.
In parallel to the rise and fall of Hilbert's program, the foundations of structural proof theory were being founded. Jan Łukasiewicz suggested in 1926 that one could improve on Hilbert systems as a basis for the axiomatic presentation of logic if one allowed the drawing of conclusions from assumptions in the inference rules of the logic. In response to this Stanisław Jaśkowski (1929) and Gerhard Gentzen (1934) independently provided such systems, called calculi of natural deduction, with Gentzen's approach introducing the idea of symmetry between the grounds for asserting propositions, expressed in introduction rules, and the consequences of accepting propositions in the elimination rules, an idea that has proved very important in proof theory.〔.〕 Gentzen (1934) further introduced the idea of the sequent calculus, a calculus advanced in a similar spirit that better expressed the duality of the logical connectives,〔Girard, Lafont, and Taylor (1988).〕 and went on to make fundamental advances in the formalisation of intuitionistic logic, and provide the first combinatorial proof of the consistency of Peano arithmetic. Together, the presentation of natural deduction and the sequent calculus introduced the fundamental idea of analytic proof to proof theory.

抄文引用元・出典: フリー百科事典『 ウィキペディア(Wikipedia)
ウィキペディアで「Proof theory」の詳細全文を読む



スポンサード リンク
翻訳と辞書 : 翻訳のためのインターネットリソース

Copyright(C) kotoba.ne.jp 1997-2016. All Rights Reserved.